Posts tonen met het label EHSQ Elite. Alle posts tonen
Posts tonen met het label EHSQ Elite. Alle posts tonen

donderdag 19 januari 2012

An example and various solutions

An example
Take the following example which hopefully demonstrates why I believe that:
  • multi-causality is a valid and usable concept (this is especially true in implementing improvements to safety systems and behaviours),
  • this may include multiple direct causes,
  • that causality not necessarily goes in strictly linear paths, but often in parallel paths that meet up at a certain point,
  • that management not necessarily is the root of all evil, and
  • causation models and tests that fit tort and criminal law definitions don’t necessarily align with prevention goals.
The case
Someone in a laboratory in a university has suffered partial loss of eyesight after he had boiling acid liquid in one of his eyes. He was not wearing the mandatory safety goggles; instead he was wearing his own glasses which he needs in order to be able to see details at working distance. He was blending two chemical substances but did not do this in the described order and volume, causing the chemicals to react more ‘enthusiastically’ than intended, causing part of the acid liquid to reach boiling point and evaporate/explode sending drops of acid liquid into the immediate area - one or several of those hitting the insufficiently protected eye.

The victim was a bit in a hurry. It was Friday afternoon and he wanted to get home as soon as possible. He just needed to get this job done; clean up his part of the lab and it would have been weekend for him. So instead of following the proper procedure he was a bit careless and used greater volumes and the wrong order (started with the ingredient he randomly picked up first). He didn’t wear safety goggles because he never does. He tried the standard issue as provided by the laboratory several times, but those fit very badly in combination with his ordinary prescription glasses, irritating nose and ears immensely. This has been reported to the department head on several occasions, by several employees without resulting in a better fitting alternative. Also suggestions to provide contact lenses that would fit with the standard safety goggles have been turned down. In addition did the victim believe that his common glasses would provide sufficient protection since they cover the area in front of his eyes. The supervisor was aware of the situation and had noticed that the victim consequently doesn’t wear his safety goggles, but chooses to ignore this fact.

The victim is experienced, properly instructed, etc. The failure to provide suitable equipment is explained by the department head with reducing his expenses to the bare minimum. He is on a tight budget (government cuts in budgets to universities and lack of corporate sponsoring due to financial crisis) and has planned to spend all the money he has on a laser-ion-mega-spectrometre which will improve his department’s possibility to do analysis of the substances they work with. Besides, the university does provide standard safety equipment in accordance to CE standards and that should be good enough. The supervisor informs us that he is fairly new in his job and used to be ‘one of the boys’ before he was promoted. He was the best qualified among the applicants and the only internal applicant filling all the formal requirements. He finds it a bit embarrassing to start picking on safety rules he hasn’t followed all that closely himself before he was promoted.

Some solutions
Many thanks to Jeff Harris and Alan Quilley for supplying alternative solutions listed below! Great to see some alternating versions and views - this only contributes to learning, there is no perfect way anyway.

Starting with my own approach, I’ll draw the incident as a causal tree, a method I prefer because it illustrates both causal connections and (to a lesser degree) chronology. In contradiction to some opinions, I would note this with two separate direct causes.


Alternatively (and fully justifiable) one could choose to see the point of “loss of control” as the direct cause and then picture the accident and its direct cause as follows:


There are certainly many other and different ways one could write down things, many of them correct. All of the relevant information in the case (so far) is present, after all. One drawback of this particular notation and combining relevant elements in one ‘box’ (i.c. the accident and the missing goggles), however, is that it’s going to be harder to explain in a logical way how the lack of goggles played a role, which it does in my opinion. But see Jeff Harris’s solution below as well!

This is for me one reason to argue that many accidents will not have linear causal relationships. There is no way in this example that you get the wrong blending of chemicals and the missing goggles in some cause/effect or why/because relationship to each other, so they must exist parallel and join up at a certain point to produce the final effect. And mind you, both are not sufficient in producing the accident in themselves. Just leaving off goggles would result in what we could call an unsafe condition, while the act of wrong blending and thus boiling/exploding liquid with goggles on would lead to what we tend to call a near miss (as far as eyes are concerned - acid in your face is no great fun either).

We could stop here, by the way, if we would follow Hart & Honore’s rule of having met a “deliberate act” (in my notation even two, parallel, acts) being a “barrier” for further investigation. That, however, would leave the questions why the victim not followed the correct procedure and why he did not wear his safety gear.

So, I choose to continue my analysis and start gathering more facts, hoping to find an answer. What we find is the following and I’ll continue with my first notation in building a visual presentation of the case, adding the next layer of causes (for our convenience I add a background showing the various phases or dominos). We see that there are three underlying causes (parallel and independent) to the not wearing of goggles: 1) a conscious decision of the victim not to use the ill-fitting safety equipment because he trusts he is sufficiently covered; 2) not supplying suitable equipment by the management and 3) the supervisor choosing not to enforce the safety rule.

I am open for suggestion and arguments here if someone does not agree on some of these being actually causes, or if some of the factors should be considered more important than others. The most crucial in my eyes would be the not supplying of suitable equipment (especially from a prevention point of view), but I have a hard time excluding the other two.

We will take this investigation even one step further. With regard to the victim’s decisions/violation/errors no relevant causal information is found. He is experienced, properly instructed, etc. So I choose not to add more underlying causes here. But the underlying managerial causes can be taken one useful step further back.


One could obviously take the analysis even more steps back, but I think that the causal connection between “budgeting process” and “recruitment of supervisors” or even “government cuts” and “financial crisis” is going to be too hazy for this case. So I choose to (slightly arbitrarily) to stop here with ‘root causes’ both on personal/employee and management/organisational level.

Jeff Harris’s version

I break the incident down into two direct causes: the cause of the incident and the cause of the injury. The direct cause of the incident was improper mixing of the chemicals. The direct cause of the injury was not wearing the "mandatory" goggles. (both unsafe acts).

Then you delve into the root causes. Why did he mix the chemicals improperly - he was in a hurry and wanted to get home - a very common theme in incidents. He was properly trained - he just didn't follow the training. So why did he not wear the "mandatory" goggles? He said they hurt his face. The company would not buy him "special" goggles to make it more comfortable. Why not? Too expensive, they said. His supervisor never made him wear goggles. Why not? Apparently the supervisor did not always wear goggles and didn't feel like he could enforce that rule on other people (no lead by example). The managers over the supervisor either did not know or did not enforce the adherence to a safety requirement.

So what to do to avoid a repeat? Start by finding out how many other safety requirements are not being followed. Start enforcing mandatory safety requirements and if supervisors are not doing their job (enforcement) maybe you need supervisors who do. I personally feel it would have been a lot cheaper and easier for the company to have bought some special goggles for the employee, but that does not relieve him of the responsibility of wearing the goggles, even if uncomfortable. (If I had a dime for every time I was told a respirator was uncomfortable!) Changing the behavior of getting in a hurry is a much harder task. There you have to reach out and engage the "hearts and minds" to change the employees' attitudes about risk and what is acceptable. You won't always succeed. That is why the safety goggles are important: to minimize the injury when someone screws up.

By the way, where is the "unsafe condition" in this case. Oh yes, the dangerous chemicals. Well, if we just shut down the lab, fired everyone, and got rid of the chemicals, this incident would not have happened. :-)

Alan Quilley’s version











woensdag 21 september 2011

Frist comment on Heinrich on EHSQ Elite

Before writing my discussion on Heinrich and Manuele there was a thread on the EHSQ Elite group on Linkedin to which I contributed.


Here's the post that triggered me:

What concerns me is SHE's continued belief in Heinrich. I would encourage all reading this thread to read "Heinrich Revisited - Truism or Myth" by Fred Manuele, published in 2002.

Heinrich's work is truly myth, including the triangle. Colleagues, please take time to read Mr. Manuele's work and then comment. The beliefs in Heinrich's myths keep us focused on less serious but frequent incidents believing that reducing their risk will somehow reduce risk of serious and fatal injuries where the exposures may be completeley different

My reaction:

Thanks for the tip on the “Heinrich Revisited” book. I wasn’t aware that it existed so I ordered it right away. I still have a copy of Heinrich’s 1941 book waiting to be read, so that’ll be two in one go… Meanwhile I checked out the Heinrich article on Wikipedia and there one can find what looks to be a good summary of Manuele’s criticism. I found some good and valid points here, but also some that I’d like to attribute to wrong understanding and the like. This activated me to sit down for some writing since I’d like to raise some critical comments myself…

The first would be that it’s rather easy to just sit there and criticize Heinrich’s work. Why not rather take the effort to update/upgrade his work to today’s standards and for example write a book “Heinrich Revised” instead? As I say often to managers and employees: It’s really easy to complain, but much more useful to take that extra step and try to improve.

It seems to be fashionable these days among some safety experts to do a bit of Heinrich bashing. What annoys me a great deal is that people tend to take Heinrich’s findings literally as if it were laws of nature (e.g. the 1-10-30-600 ratio, or whatever the distribution is, see the reference in Wikipedia to “Heinrich’s Law” - ridiculous) and then criticize Heinrich upon finding out that it isn’t. Or even worse: people posing conclusions that their own registrations aren’t good enough because they don’t live up to the “correct” ratio (I don’t make this up - happened at a forum I attended - twice within one hour!). What bullocks is that?!

Heinrich’s work at the time was plainly groundbreaking. I don’t recall anyone before him approaching safety in a semi-scientific way and leaving us at least two concepts/metaphors/models (the dominos and the pyramid) that are still somehow relevant and applicable today. Yes, certainly his work does have shortcomings. But don’t forget that we’re 80 years further down the road, have a truckload of additional safety science in our luggage and have had ample possibility to test, try, refine and partly reject his findings. Which is what a major part of scientific work is all about.

What is inexcusable, in my opinion, is when things get taken out of context and are rejected based on that wrong understanding or twisted application.
(To tackle that other Heinrich-thing in that regard: are there still people who believe that, in analogy with the brilliant and easy to explain/understand domino metaphor, all accidents are a simple and linear chain of events? Ever heard about the concept of lies-to-children?).

Let’s discuss the ratio a bit further. I still have to read it in Heinrich’s own words, but as I interpret this in the line of today’s safety science: it is totally unimportant whether the ratio is 1-10-30-600 or rather 1-25-60-500 - which probably would make a rather odd pyramid, haven’t tried to draw this. I can tell from my own experience (having the luxury of working in companies with over 15.000 to 30.000 registrations of all kinds of incidents per year and thus ample data to play with) that each incident type may have specific and probably due to circumstances changing ratios (Andrew Hale wrote at least one paper on this subject in the late 1990s/early 2000s) which may result in distributions that aren’t very pyramid shaped at all. Linda Bellamy mentioned a diamond shaped one; I would like to add an example from my own line of work. When we look at collisions of trains with track workers you have an incident type that would generate a kind of uneven hourglass. Collisions with trains are pretty binary events: either the subject dies or it’s a near-miss (rather “near hit”). There are only few ‘happy’ people hit by a train that are in need of a first aid kit or consult with a medic…

The point to be made with the pyramid is that GENERALLY (and luckily) there are only few fatal accidents, more with injuries, even more with material damage and even more near misses. Heinrich’s premises was thus that attacking the frequent low-consequence incidents will eventually reduce or prevent the number of serious accidents as well. Seems to make sense, if only because it’s pretty tedious to wait for the really strong signals to appear - much better to (re)act on weak signal and prevent the strong ones from happening at all.

Here then are at least two of the misunderstandings that often occur:

1) People tend to forget what it was that Heinrich actually counted. This (in)famous pyramid consists of data from a huge number of various incidents (wasn’t it something like 1,5 million?) which he ranged in a certain way according to the consequences resulting in this pyramid-like distribution. Meaning several things: Firstly Heinrich not only counted apples and pears; no he went out to get the entire fruit market from coconuts and bananas to raspberries and tomatoes and ranged these from rotten to ripe to green summing up these categories. The pyramid thus collects things that are very, very different in nature. Secondly let’s get another thing very clear: the pyramid is about CONSEQUENCES and consequences alone. Which gets us to point 2.

2) Often forgotten and/or misunderstood is one of the central things in Heinrich’s work, namely the Common Cause Hypothesis. This says that serious accidents and its precursors (i.e. minor incidents) are due to the same causes. Thus providing a theoretical grounding why one should do something about the “weaker signals” to prevent the serious accidents from happening. Crucial here is of course the COMMON CAUSE. Logic dictates that we will find a huge number of different causal chains (or rather tree - see the domino comment) within our fruit market (*) and looking at preventive measures that work one has to remain within one causal tree and not blend these together. It’s folly to think that preventive measures on apples will do something about the rotten coconuts (replace “apples” by “finger cuts in kitchen” and “rotten coconuts” by “BLEVE” if you like). Yet this is the un-nuanced message that is often spread by ignorant/lazy colleagues and consultants. It’s hardly Heinrich’s fault that this happens, or is it? (We could draw a parallel to religions and fundamentalism here by the way, I won’t now).
(*) Note: And likely a couple of underlying “causes” that cover a much larger selection, but these are usually so general/generic/non-specific that they are rather classification terms (think of catch-all phrases like “competence” and “culture” or the GFT/BRF from Tripod) than real causes in the chain.

Anyway, the case is: while part of Heinrich’s conclusions may not be literally valid anymore (if they ever were, literally), the general line is applicable today as much as it were then. Zooming in on a certain accident/incident type and its precursors (instead of taking a consequence as the point of departure) both a pyramid(ish) ratio (specific to each type and probably company) can be found and the common cause hypothesis can be applied. And even better: it has been scientifically tested. Sure, it took a long time since 1931, but read for example Linda Wright’s PhD (2003) and I guess the Storybuilder project in the Netherlands can provide additional evidence here.

Concluding with my own view on the title of this thread: wishing for zero fatalities is obviously a good thing but as a goal it’s useless. Just how are you going to steer on such infrequent events as fatalities or LTIs (see various eminent authors on this subject; apart from the fact that you can only go so far with controlling external factors - at least in my business). And it may do actual damage as some of our group members justly argued. In our company we rather talk about a zero-vision, not goal. Goals are to be set on the weaker signals that may lead to an accident (and eventually fatality), or rather on some pro-active leading indicators. But that was another thread, wasn’t it?